On this page
-
Text (2)
-
November 26, 1853.] THE LEADER, 1147
-
THE GEOUJSDS OF BELIEF. Westminster Bevi...
Note: This text has been automatically extracted via Optical Character Recognition (OCR) software. The text has not been manually corrected and should not be relied on to be an accurate representation of the item.
-
-
Transcript
-
Note: This text has been automatically extracted via Optical Character Recognition (OCR) software. The text has not been manually corrected and should not be relied on to be an accurate representation of the item.
Additionally, when viewing full transcripts, extracted text may not be in the same order as the original document.
Schools Of Poets Y. Poems. By Matthew Ar...
helping him forward on his road towards this aim . Such a guide the English writer at the present day will nowhere find . " Shakspeare he considers a dangerous model ( but indeed all models are dangerous to minds that " copy" them ) , and he prefers the Greeks . If his counsel be rightly interpreted , it will be useful to that large class of Amateurs who write verse but who are not " born Singers ; " but , if rigidly interpreted , it will lead the despairing classicists to exclaim with Charles Lamb , " Hang the critics , Til write for antiquity /"
Uur own behei is , that scJioois or poetry are the changing fashions of one eternal spirit ; and that good poetry is everywhere the same in its essential conditions , everywhere fluctuating with the fluctuating modes of thought and language . Further our belief is , that all conscious imitation is weakness , and that " models" produce no real good , though little harm , because the servile mind is one which if emancipated would not be strong . To study models with a view to emulate them is not the same as to study them with a view to imitate them ; the one is an invigorating—the other an enervating study . We have tarried so long over Mr . Arnold ' s preface that we must defer till next week all attempt to characterise his poems .
November 26, 1853.] The Leader, 1147
November 26 , 1853 . ] THE LEADER , 1147
The Geoujsds Of Belief. Westminster Bevi...
THE GEOUJSDS OF BELIEF . Westminster Bevieio . ITeio Series . No . VIII . October * 1853 . Art . VII . The Universal Postulate . John Chapman . According to promise we return to this number of the Westminster Review , for the purpose of considering a little more nearly the very remarkable article with the very unpromising title of The Universal Postulate . ^ It is an inquiry into the grounds of our belief in an external worldy an endeavour to reconcile Philosophy with Common Sense , not as Heid did b y the incessant assertion that Common Sense was right , but by a profound elucidation of the psychological process through which , it and all other beliefs are possible and valid . There is so much compact matter in this article that any attempt to reproduce it in the extremely abridged form necessary in , a journal like ours , runs the risk of being unreadably abstract , or else of doing the argument injustice by omissions . Let us urge the student , therefore , to read the article itself with severe attention , taking our notice as a sort of fingerpost .
Every logical act of the intellect is the assertion that something is . This is what we call belief . Each major premiss is a belief ; each minor premiss a belief ; each conclusion a belief . An argument is a series of dependent beliefs . Belief , then , is the ultimate psychological fact which we can never transcend . But it appears that there are beliefs of two kinds—some of them irresistible , indestructible ; others doubtful , untrustworthy . What is the sign by which we distinguish them ? How are we to settle , beyond cavil , the beliefs which are trustworthy , irresistible , true ? The sign is their invariablehess , in other words , the inconceivableness of the contrary . ——
" If we assign as a reason for any belief the belief on which it rests , and then assign for that belief an anterior one , and so on continuously , it is clear that we must eventually come to the end of the series—must arrive at some primordial belief of whicli no proof can be given . This remains true , whatever theory we hold respecting the origin of our knowledge . For if we say that all knowledge is organized experience , and that , in assigning one belief in proof of another , we are simply assigning a wider experience in proof of a narrower , it is clear that we cannot continue to assign wider and wider experiences in proof of each other , without arriving finally at the widest . As our experience had a beginning , it follows that ,
in tracing it backwards , we must ultimately come to our first or deepest experience —an experience which has no other to rest upon . Similarly with the hypothesis of fundamental ideas . An analytical examination of beliefs must eventually bring us down to theso ; and for these the hypothesis itself implies that no reason is assignable . Hence , whether our lowest beliefs be innate , or derived from experience , it is equally clear that , as they do not admit of proof , we can but say that they invariably exist . And whilst this fact of their invariable existence is alono our warrant for them , it at the same time expresses the necessity we are under of holding- them .
" It results , then , from all that has been said , —first , that the existence of beliefs is the fundamental fact ; and second , that beliefs which invariably exist are those which , both rationally and of necessity , wo must adopt . "
The writer then criticises Whowell and Mill on " Necessary Truths , " and after landing on the position that the beat warrant we can have for the belief \ in anything is the perfect agreement of all pre-existing experience in support of it , lie deduces the logical conclusion that the " iuconccivablencsaNof its negation" is the truest teat any belief admits of : — "If all our knowledge is derived from experience , then our notions of jtossiblc and impossible are derived from experience Possible means—not at variance with our experience ; impossible means—wholly at " variance with our experience . Olearly , unless we possess fundamental ideas , or can gain a knowledge- of things in themselves , no logical process can give to the notion , impossible , any larger meaning than this . But if , at any time , the inability of men to conceive the negation of a given proposition Himply proves that their experience tip to that
time , has , without exception , confirmed such proportion ; thon , when they . assert that its untruth if ) impossible , they really assert no inoro than when thoy assert that its negation in inconceivable . If , subsequently , it turn out that tho proposition in untrue ; and if it be , therefore , argued that men should not havo hold its untruth impossible because inconceivable , wo reply , that to say thin in to condemn the uno of tho word impossible altogether . If tho inconceivability of a thing bo eonsidored insufficient warrant for asserting its impossibility , it is implied that thoro ean exist a . sufneiont warrant ; but such warrant , whatever its kind , must bo originally derived from experience ; and if further experience may invalidate * ho warrant of inconcoivablonons , further experience may invalidate anywarrant O 1 » which we assort impossibility . Therefore , we should call nothing impossible . " In favour of this t ; ont it in urged : —
" What is tho object of any ouch test ? To iriHure a corronpondonoo between "ubjeotivo beliufH and objective facts . Woll , objoetivo facts aro over impressing t'unniHolvoH upon uh ; our experience in a register of thoso objective facts ; and the "iconceivablone . HH of ; i tiling implies that it is wholly at variance with tho register . w -15 v « h wero thin all , it is not dear how , if ovory truth is primarily inductive , ai better tost of truth eould oxint . But it inuwt bo remembered , that whilst '" any of these facts , impressing thomsolvos upon us are- occasional ; whilst others a K « 'un aro very general ; Home are universal and unchanging . These universal JH »< 1 unchanging facia are , by tho hypothotuM , curtain to establish beliefs , of which
the negations are inconceivable ; whilst the others are not certain to do this ; and if they do , subsequent facts will reverse their action . " _ It seems to us that the obscurity of this question may be somewhat enlightened if we present it under another aspect , and in lieu of considering objects as matters of Belief consider them as matters of Experience . Belief is experience ; experience of a sensation is belief in a sensation ; to have a sensation and to believe it , are not two processes but one . It is clear , therefore , that the invar tab leness ofour experience is anotherphrase for the invariableness of our belief ; and the so-called " Necessary Truths " rest on a basis as wide , but no wider , than that on which particular truths rest . When we say , " This apple is sweet , " we say our experience of this apple is that it is sweet : when we say , " Two parallel lines can . never meet , " we say our experience of two lines in parallel is that that
cannot meet without ceasing to be parallel . That " fire burns , " and that " the whole is greater than a part , " are two beliefs—two forms of our experience . Now , . as we only know through our experience , and cannot transcend our experience , the distinction between invariable and variable truths is the distinction between invariable and variable experiences . We do not believe all apples to be sweet , because our experience of apples is that some are not sweet , but the child who had never tasted apples other than sweet would believe as firmly in the essential sweetness of apples asiathe truth of a whole being greater than its part . Thus it is with Pain—or any other sensation . We cannot disbelieve in its existence so long as it exists ; no effort of the mind to conceive its negation will negative it ; we believe—ire experience it . In like manner the ever present reality of objects cannot be disbelieved ; we cannot doubfc the pain while it lads ' , and the sensation of an external world is always lasting . From this we return to our author- ' : —
" Dismissing , however , all psychological explanations , which are allowable here only as being needed to meet a psychological objection , and returning to the purely ^ abstract view of the matter , we see- —first , that belief is fundamental , and that the invariable existence of a belief is our highest warrant for it ; second , that we can ascertain the invariable existence of a belief only as we ascertain the invariable existence of anything else , by observing whether , under any circumstances , it is absent from the place in which it occurs ; third , that the effort to conceive the negation of a belief is , the looking-in the place in which it occurs ( viz ., after its antecedents ) , and observing whether there are any occasions on which it is absent , or can be made absent ; and fourth , that when we fail to find such
occasions- —when we perceive that the negation of the belief is inconceivable—wehave all possible warrant for asserting the invariability of its existence ; and in asserting this , we express alike our logical justification of it , and the inexorable necessity we axe under of holding it . Mean what we may by the word truth , we have no choice but to hold that a belief which is proved by the inconccivahlcness of its negation , to invariably exist , is t-nie . We have seen that this is the assumption on which every conclusion whatever ultimately rests . We have no other guarantee for the reality of consciousness , of sensations , of personal existence ; we have no other guarantee for any axiom ; we have no other guarantee for any step in a demonstration . Hence , as being taken for granted in every act of the understanding , it must be regarded as the Universal Postulate . "
He ' anticipates an objection : Beliefs which once were shown by the inconceivableness of their negation to invariably exist , have since been proved untrue ; and our present beliefs may one day share the same fate . Our answer i . s—the beliefs were true ; they represented the experience of mankind , which was the only tost applicable , and they had the only truth possible , viz . relative truth . But having given this answer , let us now give our author ' s : —• " There is , doubtless , force in this argument , though not bo much as at first appears . As we hinted when commenting on his position , the evidence cited by Mr . Mill , to show that inconceivable things may yet be true , is not strictly applicable evidence . There is a wide difference in nature between the cases in which the test has been found fallacious , and those in whicli we may regard it as trustworthy
—a difference arising from the relative complexities of tho conceptions involved . When , on receiving a sensation , tho subject of it finding himself unable to concoivo that he in not receiving it , asserts that he is receiving it , it is clear that he deals only with one state of consciousness , of which he simply recognises the continued existence . On the other hand , those Greek philosophers referred to bj Mr . Mill , who ' could not credit the existence of antipodes , ' who ' were unable to conceive , in opposition to old association , the force of gravity acting upwards instead of downwards , ' and who , therefore , denied that there could be men on tho other side of the earth—were dealing with many states of consciousness , and with the connexions
between them . Tlusro entered into their proposition the concepts , Earth , man , distance , position , force , and the various relationn of these to each other . Evidently , then , theso cases differ so widely , that what may bo a , legitimate test in the first , may bo an illegitimate one in the second . We must distinguish between those appeals to tho Universal Poatulato in which the action of thought is decomposable , and those in winch it is ntitlecomposabte . in proportion a » the number of concepts which a proposition involves is groat , and the mental transiLions from concept to concept are numerous , the fallibility of tho tost will increase , and will do this because the formation of the belief it separable into many steps , each of which involves the podulalc .
" And bore , indeod , wo g « t hold of the clue which leads us out of this logical mam Let it bo granted , that : i belief whioh invariahly exists , though tho inont certain possible to us , in yefc not necessarily true ? . Let it bo granted , that either from insufficient oxporienco , or from non-a ^ recmcnt between the Hubjective and the objective , the inconceivable and the impossible may not correspond even within our mental rango . Let it be granted , that for the validity even of a single undoooinjiOHablo act of thought , the Universal Postulate is an imperfect ' warrant . Let all this , we say , be granted . Still , be the test fallible or not , the probability of error in any inference will increase in proportion to tho liiiinlier of tinioM tho truth
of the test has been assumed in arriving at . it . . If the postulate be uniformly valid , it must yet happen , that as we aro liable to mental ' / . trji . iii . t , we shall occasionally think wo have its warrant when wo have not , ; ami in each ease tho chances of our having done tluY ; will vary directly as the number of times wo havo claimed its warrant , if tho postulate bo not uniformly valid , thon a further source of error in introduced , the effects of wliieh vary in tho name ratio . Honoo , on either supposition , it follows that that niuiit be the niofifc certain conclusion at which , fitartin / r from the postulate itself , wo arrive by tho fewost asauniptions of the postulate . "
Tho reader will perhaps havo hooii wliero wo Hoparato from our author ; apparently on a small point , I > ut on n point wliieh grows larger and ltvrgor as Iho argument procoeda in itt » application to Idealism
-
-
Citation
-
Leader (1850-1860), Nov. 26, 1853, page 19, in the Nineteenth-Century Serials Edition (2008; 2018) ncse.ac.uk/periodicals/l/issues/cld_26111853/page/19/
-